A number of theorists, following Heidegger, have commented upon the tendency within modernity, within the modern subject and its quest for technology and an interventionist notion of sovereign power to slide towards the limit of mechanised and planned violence that is genocide. During the furore over Salman Rushdie’s novel The Satanic Verses in 1989, the Muslim intellectual and critic Shabbir Akhtar commented upon liberal modernity's quest to dissolve difference and seek scapegoats by comparing the image of the Jew in the Holocaust to the Muslim in contemporary Europe. He famously quipped, ‘The next time we see gas chambers in
One of Agamben’s most interesting and disturbing works is Remnants of Auschwitz. Setting aside his discourse on the messianic aspects of the notion of the remnant (one that incidentally finds a poignant echo in the Shiʿi tradition in Islam), what is most striking is his examination of the figure of the Muselmann in the camp. The term Muselmann (Muslim) was used at Auschwitz to denote a passive prisoner who had given up, had no consciousness or conscience, was despised and not object of sympathy, and was a mere staggering corpse, a bundle of physicality of no consequence [Agamben 1999b: 41–43]. More importantly, he had no agency, no dignity, and was not a survivor who could testify as he was devoid of his humanity. This state of being the Muslim is the limit case, the exception, the Orientalised and objectified Other. Survivors and witnesses speak for the inhuman Muselmann and resent it [Agamben 1999b: 120]. Following Foucault, Agamben argues that racism is the process by which biopower intervenes and marks breaks within the biological continuum of humanity and reintroduces the principle of war into the system of ‘making live’ [Agamben 1999b: 84]. Yet drawing on Levi, it is only the Muselmann as the inhuman who is truly human, a paradox as the witnesses are the mere remnants; at the same time, it is the human being who can survive being a human being [Agamben 1999b: 133]. In this sense, witnesses ‘were;’ Muselmanner. Wall 1999: 1 comments on the central concern of Agamben with inverting passivity; for example, an ontological paradox for Agamben is that a thing is simultaneously itself and its qualities without being the same thing as its qualities [Agamben 1993b: 97–8; Wall 1999: 19]; similarly presence and absence, image and reality [Wall 1999: 153].
Agamben references:
Giorgio Agamben (1993a), Infancy and History: Essays on the Destruction of Experience,
tr. Liz Heron (
(1993b), The Coming Community, tr. Michael Hardt (
(1998), Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, tr. Daniel
Heller-Roazen (
(1999a), The Man without Content, tr. G. Albert (
University Press).
(1999b), Remnants of
Heller-Roazen (
(1999c), Potentialities: Collected Essays in Philosophy, tr. Daniel Heller-Roazen
(
(2000), Means without End: Notes on Politics, trs. V. Binetti and C. Casarino
(
(2004), The Open: Man and Animal, tr. Kevin Attell (
University Press).
(2005), State of Exception, tr. Kevin Attell (
Press).
1 comment:
Bonjour I'd like to thank you for such a great made forum!
thought this is a perfect way to introduce myself!
Sincerely,
Edwyn Sammy
if you're ever bored check out my site!
[url=http://www.partyopedia.com/articles/batman-party-supplies.html]batman Party Supplies[/url].
Post a Comment